The long read The
long read
‘We the people’: the battle to define populism
Illustration: Shonagh
Rae
The noisy dispute over the meaning of populism is more than
just an academic squabble – it’s a crucial argument about what we expect from
democracy. By Peter C Baker
Thu 10 Jan 2019 06.00 GMT
When populism appears in the media, which it does more and
more often now, it is typically presented without explanation, as if everyone
can already define it. And everyone can, sort of – at least as long as they’re
allowed to simply cite the very developments that populism is supposed to
explain: Brexit, Trump, Viktor Orbán’s takeover of Hungary, the rise of Jair
Bolsonaro in Brazil. The word evokes the long-simmering resentments of the
everyman, brought to a boil by charismatic politicians hawking impossible promises.
Often as not, populism sounds like something from a horror film: an alien
bacteria that has somehow slipped through democracy’s defences – aided,
perhaps, by Steve Bannon or some other wily agent of mass manipulation – and is
now poisoning political life, creating new ranks of populist voters among “us”.
(Tellingly, most writing about populism presumes an audience unsympathetic to
populism.)
There is no shortage of prominent voices warning how
dangerous populism is, and that we must take immediate steps to fight it. Tony
Blair spends his days running the Institute for Global Change (IGC), an
organisation founded, per its website, “to push back against the destructive
approach of populism”. In its 2018 world report, Human Rights Watch warned
democracies of the world against “capitulation” to the “populist challenge”.
The rise of “populist movements”, Barack Obama said in a speech last summer,
had helped spark a global boom for the “politics of fear and resentment and
retrenchment” that pave a path to authoritarianism. “I am not being alarmist. I
am just stating facts,” Obama said.
When populism is framed this way, the implication is clear.
All responsible citizens have a responsibility to do their part in the battle –
to know populism when they see it, understand its appeal (but not fall for it),
and support politics that stop populism in its tracks, thereby saving democracy
as we know it. “By fighting off the current infection,” writes Yascha Mounk,
until recently executive director of Blair’s IGC and a prominent anti-populist
writer, “we might just build up the necessary antibodies to remain immune
against new bouts of the populist disease for decades to come.”
But as breathless op-eds and thinktank reports about the
populist menace keep piling up, they have provoked a sceptical backlash from
critics who wonder aloud if populism even exists. It is now relatively common
to encounter the idea that, just as there were no real witches in Salem, there
are no real populists in politics – just people, attitudes and movements that
the political centre misunderstands and fears, and wants you, reader, to fear
too, although without the burden of having to explain exactly why. Populism, in
this framing, is a bogeyman: a nonentity invoked for the purpose of stirring up
fear. This argument has even made its way to the centrist mainstream. “Let’s do
away with the word ‘populist,’” wrote the New York Times columnist Roger Cohen
in July. “It’s become sloppy to the point of meaninglessness, an overused
epithet for multiple manifestations of political anger. Worse, it’s freighted
with contempt, applied to all voters who have decided that mainstream political
parties have done nothing for their static incomes or disappearing jobs or
sense of national decline these past two decades.”
It is hard to deny that much talk of populism obscures more
than it illuminates, and tells us more about anti-populist crusaders than any
real live populist parties or voters. But long before populism became an object
of transatlantic media fascination – before it became a zeitgeisty one-word
explanation for everything – a small group of academics was studying it, trying
to figure out exactly what it is and what lessons it holds for democratic
politics. The debate they have produced is, like many academic debates, knotty
and self-referential – and will always live in the shadow of the muddled media
and political discourse. But it helps us see that the idea of populism is
something more than just a centrist fairytale.
Thanks in large part to the persistent failure of
governments across the west to enact anything resembling a credible vision of
shared prosperity and security in the post-manufacturing era, we are now living
through a time when familiar webs connecting citizens, ideologies and political
parties are, if not falling apart, at least beginning to loosen and shift. As a
result, the question of populism is not going away. The coming years are likely
to include all of the following: more movements being labelled as populist,
more movements calling themselves populist, more movements defensively
insisting that they are not populist, and more conversations about the extent
to which populism represents the problem or the solution.
The academic debate on populism shows us that making sense
of this landscape requires more than just a usable definition of the P-word. In
short, it shows us that we can’t really talk about populism without talking
about our conflicting conceptions of democracy – and the question of what it
truly means for citizens to be sovereign.
It may be telling that very little of the public discussion
of the alleged populist threat to democracy has been devoted to the workings of
democracy itself. Perhaps we assume, without much thought, that democracy is
such a self-explanatory idea that we already know all there is to know about
the subject. Or perhaps we have come to regard democracy in its existing
western form – basically liberal democracy – as the only possible endpoint for
the evolution of politics. Populism, though it comes in many forms, always
reminds us that nothing could be further from the truth.
In 2004 a young Dutch political scientist named Cas Mudde
published The Populist Zeitgeist, a paper that proposed a new and concise
definition of populism – one that would become the backbone of academic
populism studies, a field that hardly existed at the time. Mudde was convinced
that populism was a useful concept, which meant something more specific than
“democracy, but practised in a way that I find distasteful”. He was especially
keen to challenge two common intuitions about populism: that it is uniquely
defined by “highly emotional and simplistic” rhetoric, and that it primarily
consists of “opportunistic policies” that aim to “buy” the support of voters.
Populism, Mudde argued, is more than just demagogy or
opportunism. But it is not a fully formed political ideology like socialism or
liberalism – it is instead a “thin” ideology, made up of just a few core beliefs.
First: the most important division in society is an antagonistic one between
“the people”, understood to be fundamentally good, and “the elite”, understood
to be fundamentally corrupt and out of touch with everyday life. Second: all
populists believe that politics should be an expression of the “general will” –
a set of desires presumed to be shared as common sense by all “ordinary
people”. (Implicit in this belief is another: that such a thing as this
“general will” exists.)
A populist movement, then, is one that consistently promises
to channel the unified will of the people, and by doing so undercut the
self-serving schemes of the elite establishment. As the National Front founder
Jean-Marie Le Pen put it in 2007: “I will give voice to the people. Because in
democracy only the people can be right, and none can be right against them.”
(Note how, in this formulation, there is no disagreement among “the people”.)
Or, in the more recent words of Donald Trump, speaking at his inauguration: “We
are transferring power from Washington DC and giving it back to you, the people
… The establishment protected itself, but not the citizens of our country.”
(Note how members of “the establishment” are implicitly excluded from “the
citizens”.)
For decades, attempts at clear-headed conversations about
populism had been stymied by the question of how it could be attributed to
parties and politicians that were so obviously different: how can Bernie
Sanders and Donald Trump, for example, both be called populist? In what way are
Occupy Wall Street and Brexit both possible examples of populist phenomena?
Mudde’s simple definition caught on because it has no trouble answering this
type of question. If populism is truly ideologically “thin”, then it has to
attach itself to a more substantial host ideology in order to survive. But this
ideology can lie anywhere along the left-right spectrum. Because, in Mudde’s
definition, populism is always piggybacking on other ideologies, the wide
variety of populisms isn’t a problem. It’s exactly what you would expect.
“The people” and “the elite”, Mudde wrote, are groupings
with no static definition from one populist movement to another. These
categories are, first and foremost, moral: people good, elites bad. The
question of exactly who belongs in which group, though, depends on the
character of the populist movement, and which “thick” ideology the populism
ends up attached to. A populist “people” can define itself by an ethnic identity
it feels is under threat, but just as easily by a shared sense of being victims
of economic exploitation. What matters is that it blames a perceived class of
corrupt elites; in the case of rightwing populisms, it may also heap scorn on
some underclass, whether immigrants or racial minorities, whom the elites are
accused of favouring with special treatment as part of their plot to keep power
away from “real people”.
When The Populist Zeitgeist was published, populism wasn’t a
hot topic: in all of 2005, Mudde’s paper was cited only nine times. But as the
field of populism studies has ballooned alongside mainstream interest in the
subject, the paper has become widely recognised as a classic. By a wide margin,
Mudde is now the populism scholar most likely to be cited or interviewed by
journalists – as often as not, for articles in which his definition
intermingles with the same old sloppy generalisations he set out to overturn.
Today, no academic disputes the dominance of Mudde’s
definition, especially among the growing number of scholars hoping to be part
of the conversation about populism as a global phenomenon. One major factor in
its success, in fact, is the way that it anticipated events in world politics.
The market crashes of 2008 led to the emergence of anti-austerity movements –
such as Podemos in Spain, Syriza in Greece, and Occupy worldwide – motivated by
rage at financial institutions and the small class of people who benefited from
their profits. These movements were obviously animated by a sense of opposition
between “the people” and “the elite” – but old theories of populism that
defined it specifically as rightwing, racist or anti-immigrant were
insufficiently capacious to describe these new developments in populist
politics.
The thin-ideology definition is also extremely congenial to
the landscape of contemporary academic political science, which places a
considerable premium on broad frameworks that enable young scholars to do
empirical, quantitative work. Many new scholars of populism no longer feel the
need to argue over definitions. Instead, they perform textual analyses designed
to detect how often populism’s core ideas, as laid out in Mudde’s 2004 article,
pop up in party platforms, political speeches, manifestos and tweets. Or they
administer surveys designed to track the prevalence of the core tenets of
populism in different populations, searching for profiles of archetypal
populist voters.
Every time another paper relying on the ideological
framework is published, it becomes a little more entrenched – a matter of some
frustration to the minority of academics who still think it misses the point.
The rise of the thin-ideology definition, and its increasing
influence in the still-ballooning public conversation about populism, has
consistently provoked the objections of a small but persistent camp of
dissenters within populism studies. These academics think defining populism in
terms of core beliefs is a deep methodological error: many of them also think
defining populism as an ideology runs the risk of making effective and
worthwhile political strategies seem irresponsible, even dangerous.
These academics are likely to stress the extent to which
mainstream political parties in the US and Europe have converged in recent
decades, narrowing the range of opinions that find real purchase in national
decision-making. They take as a given that this has swelled the ranks of people
who feel that what gets called democracy responds to their concerns much less
than it caters to the whims of a small, wealthy, self-dealing class of elites –
elites who vigorously deny their own complicity in this state of affairs, often
by insisting that there is no alternative.
As you might expect, these scholars tend to be most
interested in challenges to the status quo that come from the left – from “the
99%” of Occupy Wall Street and the Sanders campaign, to the “many not the few”
of Jeremy Corbyn’s Labour party – and foreground an insistence that politics is
not yet serving the correct constituency. They are also instinctively alert to
the possibility that the self-preserving centre will try to defang outsider
challenges by making anyone who endorses them appear unreasonable, frightening
and constitutionally unequipped for the sober task of governance.
This makes them suspicious of any suggestion that there is
an identifiable ideology called populism that has fundamental similarities no
matter where on the political spectrum it appears. For this crowd, talk of an
essence of populism – however thin – shades too easily into a charge of guilt
by association, which inevitably has the effect of saddling leftwing populist
movements (or even populist-looking movements) with the baggage of their
xenophobic and racist rightwing counterparts. More specifically, they are likely
to worry that the emphasis on exaggerated moralism as a defining feature of
populism makes it too easy to depict legitimate opposition to elite power as
irrational mobs.
Most objections to the thin-ideology definition owe a
substantial debt to a duo of leftist political theorists: Chantal Mouffe, a
Belgian who teaches at the University of Westminster, and her late husband, the
Argentine Ernesto Laclau. Both thinkers have directly informed the new European
left populist movements, including Syriza, Podemos and Jean-Luc Mélenchon’s La
France Insoumise.
Mouffe and Laclau’s writings on Marxism and populism – some
of which they produced together, and some separately – are famously dense and
sometimes resistant to summary. But at their core is the idea that conflict is
an inescapable and defining feature of political life. In other words, the
realm of politics is one where antagonism is natural and unavoidable, in which
consensus cannot ever be permanent, and there is always a “we” and a “they”.
“Political questions are not mere technical issues to be
solved by experts,” Mouffe insists. “Properly political questions always
involve decisions which require us to make a choice between conflicting
alternatives.” This emphasis on conflict produces a vision of democratic life
that looks more radical than typical mainstream accounts of liberal democracy –
but, Laclau and Mouffe would argue, one that more accurately describes the
actual logic of politics.
In this view, any existing socio-political order (or
“hegemony” in Mouffe and Laclau’s preferred formation, borrowed from the
Italian Marxist philosopher and politician Antonio Gramsci) is subject to
challenge. Every status quo – however sturdy – is only temporary, and can
always be challenged by a movement that seeks to replace it with something new.
Political change, in other words, is the result of demands against the existing
order, which must be fused together in a movement to change it – a movement
that may look a lot like populism.
When my demands and your demands and our neighbours’ demands
are brought together in such a movement, they can become the basis for a new
political “we”: a “people” insisting that the current arrangement of power be
altered in their name. To the extent that such a movement succeeds, it creates
a new hegemony – a new baseline – which itself becomes open to challenge over
time.
From this perspective, populism is just another word for
real politics: for people (“us”) creating together, live on the ground, a sense
of how our dissatisfactions relate, who is to blame (“them”), and how to force
a change.
But those who benefit from the status quo don’t want it to
change; to this end, they might champion toothless approaches to collective
decision-making: bipartisan consensus as an end in itself; the elevation of
“rational” experts over hot-headed partisans; “Third Way” centrism that shuns
ideological conflict in favour of “what works” or mediation by liberal
institutions. These approaches (Mouffe calls them “non-politics”) may for a
time become dominant, as they did in the Anglo-American 1990s and early 2000s.
But nothing lasts for ever, especially when the number of people who feel
politicians are making their lives more precarious is rising. And then politics
– real politics, which is to say populist politics – make a return.
Pablo Iglesias,
leader of Spain’s Podemos coalition, in June 2016.
Pablo Iglesias,
leader of Spain’s Podemos coalition, in June 2016. Photograph: Francisco
Seco/AP
Advertisement
According to Mouffe and Laclau, the only inherent connection
between rightwing and leftwing populist movements is that both embrace the same
fundamental truth about democracy: that it is an ever-shifting contest over how
the default “we” of politics is defined and redefined, in which no one
definition can be guaranteed to last. The goal, they argue, should not be
placid consensus but “agonistic pluralism”: a state in which opposition and
disagreement are accepted as the norm, and in which people maintain the
capacity to disagree intensely without demonising each other, or descending
into war.
Mouffe, in particular, has in recent years argued that the
political question of the immediate future is not how to fight populism, but
rather which type of populist you want to be. It’s about who you’re with (who
belongs in your “chain of equivalence”), who you’re against (who is causing the
problem, and how), and where to take your stand. Populism isn’t the problem:
instead, leftwing populism is the solution.
Not all the academics who take inspiration from Mouffe and
Laclau go quite this far, especially in the sober pages of peer-reviewed
political science journals. But their work is palpably motivated by a sense
that the real threat of “populism” is that our panic over the word will
foreclose the possibility of new kinds of politics and new challenges to the
status quo – and that fear of populism on the left could enable the victory of
populism of the right.
These scholars’ preference is for definitions in which it
has no ideological essence – not even the “thin” one posited by Cas Mudde. For
them, even though the thin definition readily recognises populism’s ideological
portability, it is still irrevocably tainted by pejorative overtones that push
participants in debates about populism to take a position “for” or “against”
all populisms. With no internal essence, populism is harder to categorise as
inherently good or bad. Paris Aslanidis, a Yale political scientist, calls
populism a “discourse” – a mode of talking about politics, rather than a set of
beliefs – one that frames politics in terms of the “supremacy of popular
sovereignty”.
Benjamin Moffitt, a senior lecturer in politics at the
Australian Catholic University, refers to populism as a “political style”, the
presence of which “tells us very little about the substantive democratic
content of any political project”. Under definitions of this type, the central
question is not whether a given political actor or group is or isn’t populist.
It is instead whether, from moment to moment, they are “doing populism”, and
how, and with what impact.
Of course, these disputes aren’t really about the difference
between a “thin ideology” and a “discourse.” They are about whether “populist”
is always an insult, and if the project of defining populism can ever be
disentangled from the concept’s pejorative baggage. Ultimately, they are
disputes about which types of politics make us suspicious, and why.
The current discussion of populism in the west is strongly
coloured by the populist far-right parties that emerged in Europe in the late
1980s and early 90s, such as the Austrian Freedom party, the Danish People’s
party and the French National Front. What most people knew about these parties,
at first, was that they were openly nativist and racist. They talked about
“real” citizens of their countries, and fixated on the issue of national and
ethnic “purity,” demonising immigrants and minorities. Many of their party
leaders flirted winkingly with antisemitism, and their electoral victories
coincided with a resurgence of extreme right-wing violence in Europe, such as
the 1991 attack on immigrant workers and asylum seekers in the east German town
of Hoyerswerda.
When journalists and politicians started calling these
parties and their supporters populist, the term was an expression of alarm at a
problem and, simultaneously, a euphemism that made it possible to gloss over
that problem’s exact qualities. This was especially useful for journalists who
feared being viewed as anything less than politically neutral. Populist was
obviously not a compliment, but it sounded less alarming than “extreme right”
or “radical right”. What the term seemed to communicate more than anything else
was backwardness: a juvenile incapacity to bring your preferences to the
political arena and engage in the complex give-and-take of rational compromise.
The populist combination of immaturity, emotional resentment and intolerance
was widely held to constitute a threat to postwar European democracy.
In one respect, the thin-ideology definition popularised by
Cas Mudde dismantled this view of things, freeing populism from its exclusively
far-right connotations, and cautioning against the conflation of populism with
the other -isms it was often paired to.
Mudde and many other scholars who use the ideological
definition have in fact repeatedly argued that neither Trump nor Brexit should
be regarded primarily as populist phenomena. Of course both Trump and Brexiters
used ample populist rhetoric; but in both cases, they argue, the majority of
support was motivated not by passion for populism’s core ideas, but by other
ideological factors. After the Cambridge Dictionary declared populism 2017’s
“word of the year”, Mudde wrote a Guardian column criticising the decision.
(“It has become the buzzword of the year,” he noted acidly, “mostly because it
is very often poorly defined and wrongly used.”) For the radical-right parties
whose electoral campaigns in the Netherlands, France, Germany and Austria
raised alarms across Europe, “populism comes secondary to nativism, and within
contemporary European and US politics, populism functions at best as a fuzzy
blanket to camouflage the nastier nativism”, Mudde concluded.
And yet, despite these caveats, the thin definition
nonetheless positions populism as always posing at least something of a
majoritarian threat to liberal democracy. It is this judgment, more than any
other, that keeps the fight going between scholars who adopt the ideological
definition, on one hand, and their Mouffe- and Laclau-inspired critics, on the
other.
Liberal democracy, in this context, has almost nothing to do
with contemporary distinctions between left and right. It refers, instead, to
the idea that government should facilitate pluralistic coexistence by balancing
the never fully attainable ideal of popular sovereignty with institutions that
enshrine the rule of law and civil rights, which cannot easily be overturned by
a political majority. (In this regard, as Mudde writes in his original paper,
liberal democracy is “therefore only partly democratic”.) Today, liberal
democracy is what most people mean when they talk about democracy – and
therefore, to be deemed a threat to liberal democracy is, in the context of
most political discussions, a devastatingly negative judgment.
Because populism, as described by the ideological
definition, involves a moralised conception of an absolutely sovereign “people”
– whose verdicts are regarded as practically unanimous – it is inevitable that
populist movements will come into conflict with the liberal aspects of liberal
democracy.
If all “real” people think the same way about the things
that matter most in politics, then the idea of institutional protections for a
dissenting minority are are at best superfluous and at worst nefarious. For the
populists, they are just another wall that the corrupt elite has built to keep
real power away from the people. The same is true for the independence of
judges or regulators, or checks and balances between branches of government –
especially when they appear to stymie the plans of a populist leader. In this
account, the most basic elements of liberal democracy become both kindling and
fuel for the populist fire.
No one who studies populism seriously – and not even the
most opportunistic participants in the cottage industry of anti-populist
alarmism – denies that populist movements can raise valid critiques of the
status quo, and of the very real anti-democratic power of elites. Many take a
viewpoint similar to that of the Mexican political theorist Benjamin Arditi,
who described populism as a drunken guest at democracy’s dinner party, one who
disrespects the rules of sociability and, along the way, brings up the failure
and hypocrisies that everyone else in the room has agreed to ignore. In
Populism: A Very Short Introduction, Mudde and his frequent co-author, the
Chilean political scientist Cristóbal Kaltwasser, describe contemporary
populism as an “illiberal democratic response to an undemocratic liberalism” –
one that “asks the right questions but provides the wrong answers”.
Reading critics from the left, however, one often gets the
sense that for them this adds up to so much lipstick on a pig: a sprinkling of
nuance and restraint that still leaves populism, no matter its ideological
stripe, with an undeserved taint of inherent danger. The unhappiness of these
critics is magnified by the fact that populism rarely appears in mainstream
discussion as anything but an insult – often in the mouth of pundits and
politicians who regard the left and the right as an equal threat.
The fear in these circles is that saying anything negative
about “populism” – however qualified and analytical – simply hands more
ammunition to the very people who helped make politics such a hollow,
undemocratic mess in the first place. Positioning any populism as fundamentally
antithetical to liberal democracy, in this view, simply reinforces the
association between populism and mob psychology, and stokes fears that
individual rights will always be trampled by group identities.
Some scholars in this camp now argue that we should be
talking less about populism and more about the centrist “anti-populism” that
fears and demonises it. “Just as the adulterous spouse is always the one most
suspicious of their own partner,” wrote the Italian sociologist Marco d’Eramo
in New Left Review in 2013, “so those who eviscerate democracy are the most
inclined to see threats to it everywhere. Hence all the to-do about populism
betrays a sense of uneasiness, smacks of overkill.”
For each side in this debate, the obvious temptation is to
simply dismiss the other – or to insist that what the other side calls
“populism” isn’t really populism at all, but just something populist-ish. But
to conclude that the two camps are simply talking past each other would be to
miss the extent to which they are in agreement –and what, taken together, they
tell us about the current political moment.
In 1967, when political theorists from around the world
gathered at the London School of Economics for the first ever academic
conference on populism, they had a hard time figuring out exactly what they
were supposed to be talking about. The word came from the “prairie populists”,
an 1890s movement of US farmers who supported more robust regulation of
capitalism. But in the intervening decades it had been used for a wide and
varied grab bag of phenomena from around the world, from McCarthyite
anti-communist witch-hunts in the US to charismatic Latin American leaders.
In the end, the conference proceedings failed to clarify the
matter at hand. “There can at present be no doubt about the importance of
populism,” read a summary report. “But no one is clear what it is.”
Over half a century later, there has been some progress.
Populism, specialists now agree, is an ideologically portable way of looking at
politics as a forum for opposition between “people” and “elites”. This
definition creates more questions: is the conceptual “people” of populism
inherently defined in a way that spells danger to pluralistic coexistence? Or,
less menacingly, is the idea of “the people” a necessary but always malleable
concept – simply part of what it means to do politics?
But populism, whatever it is, is not a chemical: no
scientist will ever come along and reveal its exact, objective composition.
Populism is a lens for looking at our politics, including – down a long hall of
mirrors – the politics of what gets called populist, and with what
implications.
The questions of populism would have little urgency were it
not for the widespread agreement about the shortcomings of the political status
quo: about the abyss between the shining ideals of equality and responsive
government implied by our talk about democracy and the tarnished reality of
life on the ground. The notion that “the people” are being poorly served by
politics has vast resonance across the political spectrum, and for good reason.
But what is the remedy? Among the proponents of the
ideological definition, some decline to provide an answer, claiming that they
are looking only to define and measure populism, not take a stance on it.
Others admit that, in the case of populism, the options for producing a
description without forming a judgment are basically nonexistent. The order of
the day, in their view, is to convince citizens to recommit to liberal
democracy and its institutions.
There is, however, widespread recognition in this camp –
more than they are credited with by their critics on the left – that it will no
longer suffice to insist that there is no acceptable alternative to existing
liberal democracy. Writing in the Guardian in 2017, Mudde argued that
responding to populism required more than “purely anti-populist campaigns”; it
would take, he claimed, “a return to ideological politics”. Even liberals who
want some issues to be “depoliticised” – to be removed from the realm of
democracy and handed over to experts – will have to, at a minimum, remake the
case for those decisions. Nothing can stay depoliticised for ever; that’s
politics.
If you squint just a little, this looks more than a bit like
what you would expect from Ernesto Laclau and Chantal Mouffe, with their
insistence that there is no space “beyond left and right” and no way to put
political decisions – decisions about our collective fate – outside the reach
of politics. Arguably, you might say that the defenders of liberal democracy
are being suddenly reacquainted with the need to construct a democratic “we” –
a people – around their demand to protect liberal institutions and procedures,
in opposition to radical rightwing parties who are happy to see them discarded.
The corresponding challenge for anyone further on the left
is to figure out the relationship between their long-term goals and the ideals
of liberal democracy. There have always been critics for whom liberal democracy
is sham democracy: a nice-sounding set of universal principles that, in
practice, end up functioning as smokescreens that normalise the exploitations
and inequities of capitalism.
Other theorists, Mouffe included, view something like the
European social democracy of the 60s and 70s as the precondition for whatever
comes next – for “radical democracy” that forces liberal democracy to make good
on its promises of equality. But even Mouffe is no longer optimistic about our
ability to revive our democratic prospects. Two years ago she wrote: “In 1985
we said ‘we need to radicalise democracy’; now we first need to restore
democracy, so we can then radicalise it; the task is far more difficult.” What
that task will look like on the ground is an open question.
The media framing of populism almost always sounds like a
discussion about the margins: about forces from outside “normal” or “rational”
politics threatening to throw off the balance of the status quo. But the
scholarly discourse makes clear that this is backward: that populism is
inherent to democracy, and especially to democracy as we know it in the
contemporary west. It finds life in the cracks – or more lately, the chasms –
between democracy’s promises and the impossibility of their full, permanent
realisation.
The question of populism, then, is always the question of what
kind of democracy we want, and the fact that we will never stop arguing about
this. Anxiety about populism can be a smokescreen for people who don’t want the
world as they know it to be disturbed. But it also flows from the core insight
that we can never know exactly where democracy is going to take us – not this
time, nor the next, nor the time after that.
Sem comentários:
Enviar um comentário